Monday 12 April 2021

Public Morality is not Cancel Culture

I think a distinction needs to be made between “cancel culture” and “public morality”. I judge that they are both real and observable things, and they can be distinguished. However, in my experience, they are regularly confused. Someone says “us wanting this person deplatformed isn’t cancel culture; it’s just ordinary morality”. Another says “this person shouldn’t be sacked for their views – that’s cancel culture”. Yet often those phrases – “[public] morality”, “cancel culture” – don’t seem apposite.
 
So how can we distinguish the two?
 
Public morality is that set of publicly available and acknowledged set of taboos and mores which guides and guards social behaviour both within and beyond the limits of the law. For our purposes, I really mean that component beyond the strict limits of criminal law.
 
If a neighbour’s child is nasty, you don’t let your children play with them; if you hear a shopkeeper is cruel to his employees, you shop elsewhere; if you employ someone who repeatedly airs vile views in the workplace, you are entitled to discipline and dismiss them. Even free speech absolutists tend to agree with those sorts of penalties for corrosive behaviour. (I invite any to tell me that they send their 5-year-old to the local drug den to hear all views on the subject, of course.)
 
Whatever public morality ought to contain – where the theonomist says “God’s Law” and the utilitarian says “the greater good” and the historicist says “the stable mix of current mores” – it has clear, definable features. It is predictable, known, and enforceable. We all basically know what is and is not acceptable; the situations in which such moral perils may arise are clear to all; and the likely range of consequences is explicit. There are also usually known forms of restoring someone to “neighbourness”, even if that has included, at some places and times, the use of the gallows to put someone back within the social pale.
 
“Cancel culture” does not share these features. Though it is chiefly a feature of the cultural left, it can influence though from any segment of society, so it has no specific moral content – it not simply the taboos of one sect or another. Any view or behaviour that is controversial amongst a subset can be punishable by it. But that is one aspect – “cancel culture” very often operates upon contestable views or behaviour, not on the universally abhorred. Only the subset disapproves. These are not public and known taboos, on the whole.
 
Think of Nicholas and Erica Christakis, whose crime was that they consistently defeated free speech and expression at Yale – by defending both satire of the institution and its wealthiest attendees by minority-background students, and arguing against regulation of Halloween costumes. Fairly innocuous views, both – but both controversial to subgroups, and the latter a cause celebré that signalled the rise of “cancel culture”, as students campaigned for the Christakises to be disciplined.
 
The contented nature of sins which excite “cancel culture” is only one feature. Another is the endlessly shifting nature of what constitutes crimes and what is considered appropriate punishment. Public morality is not just generally agreed, but also public and explicit, even if it may transmogrify over time – it is a slow and fairly reliable process, whether or not one likes any given feature of it. Cancel culture invents crimes on the spot. The New York Times parted company with respected reporter Donald McNeil for using the N-word some two years prior – but not as a slur. McNeil was, by his own account, responding to a student’s question about their own historic (when 12 years old!) use of the slur, and so asked something like “Have you ever used [the N-word] in other contexts?” This was no sort of “knowable sin” even in 2019; it was on a private retreat; it was in the context of advising a vulnerable high school student about whether their old (frankly very minor) sin might have a long shadow. This exercise of grace on McNeil’s part led to an internal letter of 150 NYT employees demanding his apology, and led to his sacking.
 
It is not just the punishment that does not fit here – as absurd and wicked as it obviously is – but the crime does not, either. The accusation against McNeil is one of racism, but no one really claims he used the word as a slur. His greater sin, which caused the internal letter campaign, seems to have been that he off-handedly dismissed the accusation by telling the Washington Post “Don’t believe everything you read”. What crime was McNeil punished for? Like a character in Dostoyevsky or Kafka, nothing in the trial is open to rational enquiry: neither the alleged crime, nor the process of arrest and investigation, nor the final punishment.
 
A last feature of “cancel culture” contrasted to public morality can be seen through the examples of Christakis and McNeil. An inordinate focus of “cancel culture” is on two things: the need for ideological self-abasement by the wicked, and their employment status.
 
Public morality, when acting outside of criminal law, usually limits itself to social relations, unless there is a specific problematic behaviour in the workplace. Cancel culture invariably seeks alteration to employment relations – disciplinary procedures, reorganizations, firings. (Indeed, insomuch as it is a culture much more prevalent on the cultural left, a connection can be drawn – employment is connected to “equity”, and so the wicked do not deserve their jobs. Justice is a raw mathematical exercise, and it relates as much to your skin colour or gender as to your actual sins.)
 
Similarly, social restitution in public morality does not require swearing public adherence to the ideology of subgroups without any connection to the activity undertaken. That is, to remain in your Model Railway Club after some contretemps, you may need to say you care about Model Railways; the connection between being a education researcher like Eric Christakis and needing to support the control of Halloween costumes seems much more tenebrous.
 
We need to learn to distinguish between public morality and cancel culture so that we can defend ordinary social relations, freedom of association, and the rest, whilst being able to meaningfully critique the – ah – structurally unjust machinations of cancel culture. So let me conclude by offering practical “examples” of each.
 
The people of Trendia have always eaten babies. An emerging consensus, however, stands against eating babies; the law changes to remove the VAT exemption on edible babies. It becomes less acceptable to partake. Those relative few who continue experience social consequences, in time, from those who find it an obnoxious habit. They are not invited to dinner by Abstainers as often. A workplace which has a rule banning eating babies on the property disciplines the Baby-Eater for repeatedly consuming them at work, in open defiance of the clear rule. The Baby-Eater may continue eating babies, socialising chiefly with other Baby-Eaters, but accepting limitations in public spaces – or they may join the Abstainers. Perhaps this time public morality is wrong – but in time it may shift again, by slow but clear processes.
 
In neighbouring Fadland, the people also eat babies. Well, actually, now they don’t, as of yesterday. Or at least, some of them don’t (quite rich, influential figures with platforms). But you know what I just heard? A philosophy professor defended eating babies five years ago in a debate. Yes, he was just taking a side for the purpose of the debate, but can’t he see how much harm he was doing? Yes, I was eating babies at the time, so what? I couldn’t help it; I have many extenuating circumstances; but the Professor was powerful and should have known better. He needs to be sacked now. Can I have his job, please?