Wednesday 30 October 2019

Culture Shocks – Mad Men, Tobacco, and the Conquest of the Past


The past is a foreign country, and like other foreign countries, may be invaded and conquered if sufficient vigour is shown. This is one of the effects of the rash of neo-period dramas over the last decade or so; the past has been more thoroughly recast for our consumption than in any previous period, because the mass media budget is there for it. We see the past a vast treasure trove of stories we can tell - all entirely ours to tell how we wish. But why? In the least historically grounded society in history, why are we so fascinated by the past? (That may be a little too loaded a question, I grant.) And why is there so much smoking?

I do not pretend to be a Mad Men expert. I have watched most of the first season, and I have read virtually nothing about it. Nonetheless, it is a fascinating case study. We are shown middle-class America in 1960; the men are nearly uniformly sexist, the women brittle and oppressed, the children neglected, and every white person is casually racist to black and Jew alike. Our hero is an impersonator, a working boy made good, a serial adulterer, and nonetheless the character who seems to treat minorities and women most decently. He’s a destructive liar, but much more admirable than all the socially conservative villains around him. Also, did I mention, everybody smokes, all the time?

The past was a dark place, it turns out. And yet – and surely this is the theme of most Mad Men long-form essays, statistically speaking – it is all presented so beautifully. Perhaps we are to take away that the beauty and order is sugar-spun and false, as we are to take Betty Draper’s public persona. But if that’s the simple fact of the matter, why does everyone look so cool smoking?

Smoking is ubiquitous in any modern production of anything set mid-century. Yes, there was plenty of smoking back then, but this much? And in every scene, every moment? Mad Men’s creator, Matthew Weiner, was born in 1965; he can scarcely know the habits of the professional class in the office during the 1960s, no matter the voluminous research he and his team plainly undertook.

But of course, that is not the point. The smoking is meant to signal that we are in the past, and it is meant to be part of the glamour, just like the tailored suits and beautiful cars. One of the more prominent ladies in season 1, Rachel Menken, has glossy black hair and smokes using a holder. Audrey Hepburn is not meant to be far from our minds.

I do not know that it is conscious, but the smoking also articulates the view we have of the past, especially as we compare it to the present. Smoking kills, yes – and Mad Men constantly winks at this fact – just as 1960 was rife (in our view) with sexism, racism, and classism. But wasn’t it all more civilised then? Weren’t the cars nicer? Weren’t the outfits just swell? And wasn’t the smoking cool? Mad Men is, as for zeal, a persecutor of the old guard; as to righteousness before the media jury, blameless. But it cannot help but be wistful for the past it is glad to be escaping. You will find the same in any period drama of the last decade or more, I think.

As we float off from our moorings, we look back wistfully; our anxieties about postmodernity are well-founded, but we are sure there can be nothing morally worth salvaging from these prior times. And yet – and yet – for all we know the past is cancerous, it is so appealing. Nothing now tastes so good, or looks so good. Perhaps we’ll get our fix, our passive smoke, by watching programmes with all the right morals, but which titillate us by giving us the external beauty of a former age. (We have no language to comprehend the inner beauties.)

There is an irony to all this, it should be noted. The 1950s – ending as our programme starts, and the morality of which we are asked to gawp at in horror – was a modern decade, not a premodern one. Betty Draper is depressed by the fragility and falseness of suburban community, and left without serious purpose as a housewife – precisely because of her mod cons, not in spite of them. The strange mix of a wife with a serious education at Bryn Mawr and a lack of full-time staff to handle the cooking and children is the result of a booming, growing middle class and a spreading of wealth. And so, too, the smoking – precisely at its peak in the early 20th century, not beforehand. Our lack of mooring means we long, not for a different world, but our own yesterdays – and we do not realize it.

The world and morality we are called to reject by Mad Men are our own, not that of the distant past. This is not a subtle point being made by the show; it may believe we still suffer from sexism and the rest, but it would hardly deny great progress had been made. It is entirely accidental that it assaults the very society that first affirmed the key values we rely upon now. Comfort, independence, self-realization were the creed of the ‘50s and ‘60s, over against virtuous labour, community, and self-sacrifice. We look at what we believe is the past, and feel uncomfortable with what we see, without realizing that we are in front of a mirror. In our conquest of the past, we have remade it entirely in our image.

Thursday 17 October 2019

The English Constitution Explained, II: Sources of the Constitution


Contents
Parliament and its Sovereignty
The Rule of Law
Convention and Law
Decline and Fall


The Sources of the Constitution
We must first deal with what we actually mean when we say “the English constitution”. The English constitution is part written, part convention, but not entirely codified – that is, there is no one single document which collates with force of law the essential holdings of the constitution, as is the case with the US Constitution and its Amendments. When we want to discover what laws and conventions are pertinent – which voices speak under the tree, if you will – we turn to two sources: laws, statutes, key judicial rulings, and so forth; and authorities, who synthesise the former and add to them conventions.

These are the building blocks which have been formed by our ancestors into the edifice in which we now stand, to use another metaphor. Our constitution is a great cathedral in which our body politic meets; it has been accreted to, and changed, but largely in line with its purpose and a common architectural tradition. Now, however, we have all been relocated to the pokey Brutalist extension with the café and meeting rooms, which is evidently entirely out of place. For forty-something years we have sat on plastic chairs under strip lights drinking weak tea. No wonder so many are unsatisfied with our constitutional arrangements! Worst of all, very few even know what is next door, behind the strangely ornate wooden double doors; very few have even been into the cathedral itself. Considering the sources of our constitution is, then, opening those doors and stepping into the nave, and then exploring the chapels and cloisters. We may suffer vertigo, or a sense of foreignness, but let us at least consider it as an alternative to the chipboard café tables.

For a simple list of sources, read a textbook introduction to this subject; here we shall try to discern the key artistic themes and engineering principles of the cathedral. Which laws and rulings bear the weight of the marvellous ceiling? Which authorities have decorated the corbels and monuments? We must be necessarily selective, but one hopes a clear picture will emerge – of real continuity, of wise development, and of common principles of rights and of stewardship spread over 700 years of growth. Rather than offering lists of laws or rulings, I will instead offer certain two key features of the constitution – its “royal and political” nature and the idea of the inheritance of rights – and point to key exemplars of those features. Then I will discuss the role of authorities. My intention is to show how the individual leaves and branches of the tree build up to a constitution, rather than atomistically delineate them, cutting off the leaves and pressing them into a display book.

A“Royal” and “Political” Constitution
A defining feature of the English constitution, over against (say) the ordinary manner of working in France, whether before or after the Revolution, is that the English constitution is both “royal and political”, as Fortescue put it in the 1470s. France before the Revolution had chiefly a “royal” constitution, and after has chiefly had “political” constitutions. The “political” here emphasizes the assent of the people, the “royal” the decision-making right of the executive. Of course there will be a mixture of elements in all constitutions, and we are not to take the word “political” to mean, necessarily, democratic, nor the word “royal” to mean, in all situations, a single monarch.

But we can see in England this mixed form even before the Conquest. The King seems to have, even as early as 600 AD, needed consent from the Witenagamot – really a semi-formal gathering of aristocrats and clergy rather than a formal, permanently established council – on a number of questions. Certainly it is reported from the 10th century that the hereditary heir technically needed affirmation from the Witenagamot to take the throne, and Kings often seem to have cooperated with their magnates on the passing of law codes and specific legal measures. The King usually initiated policy, but – to greater or lesser extents, depending upon the strength of the throne – this relied on a pragmatic dealing with the power-brokers of the realm.

It is this same principle – that some significant tranche of society has a formal or semi-formal role in counselling upon and assenting to laws created and enacted by a robust executive power – that should inform our understanding of the great statutes and rulings that underpin the constitution. We see it in the self-selecting, self-perpetuating council of 25 barons created by the Magna Carta to ensure the enforcement of the Charter; we see it in the plausibility of De Montfort's rebellion; we see it the late Lancastrian councils, and in Henry VIII's populist claims of Parliamentary support for Reformation; it is the very wellspring of the claims of the Petition of Right and the Five Members and the Declaration of Rights – but also of the invitation by Parliament to Charles II to return to England and ascend the throne. The Rump Parliament preferred the ancient Crown to the new Major-Generals and considered the old balance – however imperfect – much to be preferred to the new-fangled progressivism of a military junta, which so openly overthrew the “political” element of the constitution. Any traditional constitutional defence to be made in favour of the Great Reform Act, or the Representation Acts, or the Parliament Acts, can only be made on the same basis – that they seek to the right balance between “royal” and “political”, without abolishing either.

It ought to be noted here – to follow on Fortescue's comparison with France – that of course we might note the importance of magnates in France, we might consider the Parlements as a loose parallel to our own Parliament, we might remember that absolute monarchy is always half a fiction, relying as it does on a vast bureaucracy with its own interests. But none of these were truly “political” in terms of their formal footing or purpose. The magnates had no formal right of affirmation – as the Witenagamot did – nor a chartered duty to protect enumerated rights, as with the Magna Carta Barons. The Parlements were judges, and in no way meant to represent the body politic – they were essentially an extension of the royal bureaucracy, even if they sometimes worked in their own interests. That vast bureaucracy, as we may quickly infer, was only ever an extension of the executive, of the royal power – that the whole royal power might sometimes fall out amongst itself is no proof that it was a “political” element of the constitution.

The Inheritance of Rights
The formal, binding sources of the constitution, then – whether statute or ruling – uphold both “royal” and “political” elements. But why? Why this form? Is it a self-evident truth? Are the respective rights of the royal and of the political inscribed on the human soul? This brings us to another important principle of how we identify the sources of the constitution. The English constitution is quite different from the American iteration, or the various modern declarations of human rights. The English constitution does not recognize the phrase “that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their creator with certain unalienable rights”; not because it does not believe in a Creator (far from it!), or that men are not endowed with natural dignity by that Creator. Rather, it is because legal and political rights are matters of tangible property, not spiritual reality. A spiritual reality may inform what tangible property is recognize, but the two are not to be entirely identified. Sometimes, indeed, our constitution finds it right to affirm the tangible property even where a spiritual reality is lacking.

Let me offer two examples: when someone in Government, such as the Monarch, is incompetent or morally lacking, we respect their rank though we are tempted to disrespect their person – we affirm the tangible property, of power and rank, even as we recognize that the corresponding spiritual reality is lacking in them; or again, when we affirm equality before the law, we do not consort with the fiction that all persons are created equal in any real sense (How many people are wiser or nobler than you are? How many stupider or morally inferior to you?), but rather accept the unearned property right of all Englishmen to legal equality. Just as we might feel irked by a buffoon inheriting a fortune but accept he has a legal right to, we ought to accept that an obvious rogue has his rights in law even though mob justice would be quicker and easier. His right to jury trial is not contained within him; it is not a matter of DNA. It is an inheritance.

Before I turn to iterations of this in law itself, this is the right time to bring up Burke's great concept of England as a commonwealth of those living, those who have died before now, and those who are yet to be born. I have mentioned this in the Introduction, but it is important to mention here because it is Burke who makes the most sustained argument that our constitution is one of inheritance; its sources are not isolated Acts but the whole fabric, every right passed down to us by our forebears. It was on this very basis that Burke supported the American Revolution but was aggressively critical of the French iteration's ideas spreading to England. The Americans were born Englishmen, possessed of the rights of their forefathers; they fought for what they owned, as far as Burke was concerned. There was, we might say, no real “political” element in their relations with their mother isle – merely a “royal” one. They were right, therefore, to fight for their rights. On the other hand, the French Revolution dissolved all ideas of rank and wilfully shattered bonds of property via confiscation. Its English supporters claimed the English Monarchy was only sustainable by its being derived from an ongoing popular affirmation1. It was, in essence, a democratic monarchy; it relied for its authority on the active permission of the masses. Burke demolishes this idea, and all those of his opponents. Inheritance is the very basis of the English constitution; our monarchy exists by inheritance by this very principle; every right we have was worked for by our forefathers, and passed to us. (And here the Chartists and their modern descendants agree; to the traditional English socialist, the rights of the worker have been fought for and won, rather than discovered by philosophical deduction.)

We can see that the principle of assent gained by the Crown from the Estates of the land goes back to pre-Conquest times. Any baron or bishop thereafter claiming some right to consult with the King would surely be aware that they followed in that tradition (and could point to the very different but parallel development of the Electors of the Holy Roman Empire). However, this was once for all established by the Great Charter of 1215. There King John declares (in the translation provided by the British Library): “TO ALL FREE MEN OF OUR KINGDOM we have also granted, for us and our heirs for ever, all the liberties written out below, to have and to keep for them and their heirs, of us and our heirs”. The “royal” element of the constitution has granted a set of liberties, of freedoms, to be enjoyed by their free subjects and their heirs. How does one receive these liberties? By turning to Rousseau or Paine? By no means. One receives them by inheriting them – that is, by being an heir. Alternatively – implicitly – by becoming a free subject. The immigrant upon naturalisation gains these liberties as if they had been born to the soil2.

Of course, King John is in part merely recognizing rights already extant – we may easily descry the Witenagamot in the Baronial Council, that first proto-Parliament – and this impression is only reinforced when we realize that the Magna Carta (Great Charter) is so-called because its issuing by John's son, Henry III, was accompanied by another law, the Charter of the Forest. This Charter reversed royal arrogation of property rights in the countryside, returning the use of land to those who had been “accustomed” to such rights. Rights here are a matter of custom; they are exterior, not interior, to the holder of the rights. So, too, adducing the analogy, are the famous Magna Carta liberties – as, for instance, due process and trial by jury (article 39 in Blackstone's numbering) or the concept of proportionable punishment (article 20).

We see the same principle offered as the basis of the Declaration of Rights in 1688 and the near-identical Bill of Rights in 1689 – the other great description of the liberties of the English subject, after Magna Carta. Its precursor, the Petition of Right in 1628, had leant heavily upon the Great Charter as the source of rights still enjoyed by Englishmen (for instance, and most particularly, the matter of due process and trial by jury); now, the Lords Declarant invited William and Mary to assume the throne, and alongside that, listed their grievances, “Vindicating and Asserting their auntient Rights and Libertie”. They believed that their rights were not metaphysically endowed, but ancient and inherited. The rights enumerated – the supremacy of Parliament, free elections, the right to bear arms – were, in a word, property.

Here we may turn to some of the great discoveries of Common Law by our Courts. What of the Case of Proclamations (1610) or Entick v Carrington (1765)? They both limit arbitrary power, and the latter establishes the principle that courts may review non-Parliamentary acts of the executive. On what basis? To put it a different way – is the reasoning deductive, from philosophy or theology, or is it inductive, from the nature and iterations of the common law? Surely the latter. The King was found in 1610 to be unable to proclaim new offences – because this was the natural growth or development of the constitutional settlement. It was a truth incipient in the constitution already; only the crisis of the Proclamations led to its articulations. The Home Department was found in 1765 to be unable to conduct arbitrary raids, because they violated the historic rights of the Englishman.

Authorities and Conventions
Having highlighted a selection of statutes and rulings by reference to the two great cornerstones of the English constitution, how ought we consider the authoritative writers of the tradition? When Sir Edward Coke sat on the bench during the Case of Proclamations, he wrote law; but when he wrote his great Institutes, did he merely offer constitutional opinion? Is Dicey's great Law of the Constitution an authority because it is still significantly factually relevant now, for all the great changes that have occurred over a century? Or is there some other reason?

Here we do enter upon a mystery, and one not quite pleasing to the most modern of modern eyes. How is it possible that some think that Burke did not merely articulate a view of our constitution, but in his writing embodied and reified it? Why is the blend of cynicism and romantic traditionalism we find in Bagehot and Dicey more than mere personality, so that it ascends to the status of being a frame in which the constitution may (partly!) be viewed? There is no neatness here. Our earlier image of the Great Tree helps; these writers are voices under the tree. In a constitution based on inheritance, based on transmission and slow development, they are the voices handed down to us as authoritative. They are authoritative not merely for their factual accuracy or argumentative force, but because they are settled upon us as the spokesmen of the past in our great commonwealth. They have been elected as representatives by generations past; they are recognised as the rightful incumbents. We have no more right to deconstruct them than we do our great-grandparents, and no more right to defy the expressed will of the dead in their election than we have in barring from the Commons MPs whose parties we disagree with.

It is in this light that we ought to see the books on our shelves – not for us to obsequiously bow to, but for us to reverently hear. It is they who strengthen our sense of which conventions and which understandings we ought to have of constitutional matters; they form the majority voice, over against – to take my example in the Introduction – the absolutism of Charles Stuart or the radicalism of John Lilburne. We reject their wisdom at our peril.

I mention conventions; conventions are those procedures and ways of working that have not achieved status of law but which are, where uncontradicted by law, binding upon our system. It is chiefly, one way or another, through our authorities that we know what these conventions are. If statutes and rulings are the “house rules” of our great estate, conventions are our table manners and, in an abstract sense, our choice of wallpaper; they smooth out our dealings and decorate our proceedings. That Black Rod raps upon the door is superfluous and in legal terms perpetuates what has become a fiction (a balanced relationship between Crown and Commons), but it is nonetheless a curtain which protects the delicate mysteries of our constitution.

You may ask, incidentally, which authorities have been so elected by the dead. To begin with, let your bookshelf start with the Magna Carta, Burke's Reflections, Bagehot's English Constitution, and Dicey's Law of the Constitution. Then find a modern book of Reports on key rulings, print out the text of the 1689 Bill of Rights, and add Sir John Fortescue's two treatises. Further reading should add Sir Henry Maine's Popular Government and Stephen's Liberty, Equality, Fraternity from the latter jurists, and Sir Edward Coke's writings to represent the former – both rulings and treatises (there is a 3-volume set from Liberty Fund, now out of print but available second-hand). Finally, you might seek out De Republica Anglorum by Sir Thomas Smith, any cheap-ish translation of de Bracton's seminal rulings and opinions, and perhaps even the voluminous Blackstone (a collater of and commentator upon laws and rulings, published first in the 18th century) and the expensive Erskine May (who wrote Parliament's rulebook).

An astute reader will note that the final statute mentioned above is from the 1940s (the 2nd Parliament Act). The last authority mentioned by name is Dicey, whose last edition was in 1914. Surely the 1973 European Communities Act is a key statute, and Factortame (1990) the most important ruling in modern history? Of course. But let me plead two excuses for not mentioning them earlier: first, in an 800 year old constitution which relies upon inheritance and is a commonwealth of the living and the dead, the last 45 years must necessarily have a lesser role and a more limited voice; second, as I shall examine in the final essay in this series, as we meet under the tree to consider these more recent events, we have cause to think that these are poorly-directed branches – or even alien impositions of steel and plastic, warping our growth.


1 Distinct from a monarch being affirmed or voted in by an aristocracy, as with the Witenagamot or any modern indirectly elected President. For more on how all governing classes are aristocracy, see my essay on that topic.

2 This point allows us to note that the English value soil, but generally have not emphasized “blood”; there is no Volk who have a natural superiority or implicit right to rule. The English are not in this sense a race apart, but a legally defined set of property-owners. Rights are the inherited property, and legal forms permit them to extend beyond the immediate family descent, much as certain Letters Patent of nobility have allowed the title to leave the original line.

Thursday 3 October 2019

The English Constitution Explained, I: Introduction


The English Constitution Explained
Contents
Parliament and its Sovereignty
The Rule of Law
Convention and Law
Decline and Fall

Introduction
In the midst of its final collapse and death1, it has become clear how thoroughly misunderstood the English Constitution has been by its beneficiaries and supposed guardians. Of course, insomuch as the entire tendency both of our nation's educational system and the grand political project to which we have been attached for the last 40-something years has been to dissolve our connection with the past, our knowledge of ourselves, we ought not be surprised that we have become not merely unmoored from our constitutional system, but also become – even amongst our lawyerly class – utterly ignorant of it. The purpose of these essays will be, then, to offer an explanation of where the English constitution comes from and what its main features are.

I should state three matters in this introduction that will save the reader much distress were they to be surprised by their discovery later on.

Firstly, I do not pretend this is a merely “neutral” explanation; in fact, I deny that there could be any such thing. As a rule of thumb, you may immediately distrust anyone who presents themselves as strictly neutral when reporting or explaining some matter, as if they had no grand ordering assumptions about reality or the nature of communication, let alone the facts at hand. I would also suggest that it is in fact undesirable for someone to seek to be merely “neutral”, insomuch as such an attitude is not just doomed, but unlikely to inject any vigour or passion to proceedings. As Chesterton put it, education is not a noun describing an object (like “kettle”) but a method (like “transmission”). No educational activity can be neutral, because the result of it lies in the content, chosen by the educator for its importance to achieve an end result. Ends are determined by values; values are never neutral.

However, I will seek to be balanced, just, and honest. Neutrality is no virtue, but justice and honesty are. Balance here means seeking to weigh matters in due proportion to their importance; justice means giving due time to competing views, where the views each have a claim on our time; honesty means not glossing over the lumps and bumps of the constitution too quickly, so as to suit the wider argument. But I am avowedly not neutral.

These essays constitute a defence of our constitution; they very likely will also be a very minor and unimportant obituary to it. They stem from a love of the way we have done things on this island for 800 or more years. Underlying them is a conviction that, for a people so fitted as we have been, our processes have been properly matched, and that recent large-scale deviations from them have been to our great detriment.

The nature of the discussion means it is hard to explain why I believe these things to be true without explaining the constitution itself, and even the explanation can only be a partial argument in its favour; my love is of the flourishing oak tree itself, not of a botanical abstraction. Even having lived at the foot of a lightning-shattered geriatric, as anyone my age has done their whole life, cannot wholly obscure its power and beauty from us; the roots still run deep; and perhaps one or two final acorns survived the strike and could fall to grow somewhere else.

This image brings me on to my second preliminary declaration: the English constitution relies upon authority, and a specific type of authority – that of tradition, of inheritance. Moreover, one is not to envision the great English philosophical and constitutional tradition as merely a set of dead rules, left to descendants entirely separated from their forebears. Our constitution is like any inheritance; the fine armoire in the corner is not just wood carved and decorated for the purpose of storage. It is alive with ghosts. So it is with our constitution now – even as we founder on the rocks, the water pours below, the rudder is wrecked, and the masts fall, Denzil Holles stands on the gun deck calling for men to the buckets; the Marquess of Halifax and Fitzjames Stephen gather marines to see off the scavengers and robbers now seeking to board us for our cargo; and Burke – most of all, Burke – stands on the quarterdeck, firm in the storm, seeing the narrow path forward to salvaging all, and directing the crew to what is needed to do so.

And if you don't know those names, look them up.

I have used the image of a tree to describe our constitution; let us return to that. The roots are deep – from Alfred and the Conquest and the Great Charter down to now. The tree has been carefully tended much of that time, with bad growths sawn off, with better branches carefully managed and trained to flourish in the right direction. There have been times of neglect, but it is still the same tree. We may dispute which strategy we think best to maintain the growth of the tree, but it is still the same tree. We, our ancestors, and our posterity all stand under the great branches which give us cover from sun and rain, which bear fruit for us to eat, and we debate – the dead and unborn not silent here – what is to be done. My great-grandchildren stand under that tree, and I exercise prudence on their behalf to maintain it, listening carefully to their quiet voices.

I warn you that this is what our constitution is for two reasons: 1) to protect the tender feelings of those loathers of authority and tradition who might faint at the idea if unwarned – I hope I thereby forestall any offence at such antiquated notions as tradition, coming as they do with the territory; 2) to assert the fact – and it is a fact – so as to make clear that my whole idea of nations and constitutions is both transcendent, not bound by time, particularly by one atomised moment in time, but grounded in eternity; yet also utterly immanent – the English constitution is not an abstract idea, or a proposal for anyone else, but the specific birthright of the English nation and its gift to the wider United Kingdom. This immanence further means – taking the image of the tree – that I am here seeking to trace the lineaments of the actual tree, of the right line of inheritance, of the great tradition; I will therefore be making judgements about what this is. In that, for instance, Charles Stuart and John Lilburne both will be considered minority voices, though undoubtedly they may still speak at the foot of the tree.

(I should note here, mentioning the United Kingdom that of course I am speaking of the English constitution; I grant my Scottish compatriots that, until 300 years ago, they had their own constitution, and their own workings of law, partially parallel to England and partially inspired by Continental models. The historic Irish constitution is more closely tied to England, but carries its own set of difficulties. Though I love our Union, and believe every part has benefited to greater or lesser extents since the Acts of Union, it must be granted that our friends will ultimately decide on their own arrangements, and that these may differ from the arrangements they have had for 300 and 200 years respectively. Different peoples are fitted for different institutions; sensible conservatism loves and affirms variety. It is with the common system, however – the English constitution – that I deal.)

Of course, all nations, all constitutions, all laws, rely upon this same concept of continuity and transmission – even where things have changed greatly, they are the same peoples with the same great tradition. As Orwell puts it, if we want to imagine how Spain now is the same as Spain in 1800, consider yourself – you are quite different now from when you were 5, but you are still the same organism. Without tradition having authority, political and social life is quite impossible, unless it be enforced by naked force – and that very force will destroy it.

Thirdly, this is an essentially theoretical work. I may, given time and reason, write about some proposals of restoration (which, I warn the reader, will be even more shocking and unpleasant than the use of the word “tradition”), but these essays are about what the English constitution has been. They are about what, before its present decline, maintained it and led it to flourish even after hundreds of years of development, so that Hallam could say in the early 19th century that it only then seemed to be reaching true blossom, after 600 or more years of growth.

As I have said, the theory is not simply a theory of the abstract; a theory of a theory. It is an attempt to “spectate” (thus the etymology of theory) upon the history of the thing. And a theoretical approach can accomplish multiple aims – not simply description, but defence, and of propagation; to return to what I said above about being just and honest, this includes being just to the dead whose estate we temporarily inhabit, and honestly romantic about our inheritance, which we have so nearly lost.

1 I begin writing this in September 2019.